text
stringlengths 277
5.29k
| textbook_name
stringclasses 16
values |
---|---|
mon good is identified with acting justly or attending to the inter
ests of all members of a society in a spirit of impartiality. This
identification of the 'common good' with justice is not universally
accepted. See Sidgwick, 17ze Method of Ethics, chap. 3路
NOTES
301
Page I 67. Moral obligation. For the need to distinguish the obligation
and duties of social morality both from moral ideals and personal
morality, see Urmson, 'Saints and Heroes' in Essays on Moral Phi
losophy (Melden ed.); Whiteley, 'On Defining "Morality"', in 20
Ana{ysis (I96o); Strawson, 'Social Morality and Individual Ideal' in
Philosophy (I96I); Bradley, Ethical Studies, chaps. 5 and 6.
Page I 69. 17ze moraliry qf a social group. Austin in 17ze Province uses the
expression 'positive morality' to distinguish the actual morality
observed within a society from the 'law of God', which constitutes
for him the ultimate standards by which both positive morality and
positive law are to be tested. This marks the very important distinc
tion between a social morality and those moral principles which
transcend it and are used in criticism of it. Austin's 'positive mo
rality', however, includes all social rules other than positive law; it
embraces rules of etiquette, games, clubs, and international law, as
well as what is ordinarily thought and spoken of as morality. This
wide use of the term morality obscures too many important distinc
tions of form and social function. See Chapter X, s. 4路
Page I72. Essential rules. See Chapter IX, s. 2, for the development
of the idea that rules restricting the use of violence and requiring
respect for property and promises constitute a 'minimum content'
of Natural Law underlying both positive law and social morality.
Pages I 72-3. Law and external behaviour. The view criticized in the
text that whereas the law requires external behaviour, and morality
does not, has been inherited by jurists from Kant's distinction be
tween juridical and ethical laws. See the General Introduction to
the Metaphysic of Morals in Hastie, Kant's Philosophy qf Law (I887),
pp. I4 and 20-4. A modern restatement of this doctrine is in
Kantorowicz, 17ze Definition qf Law, pp. 43-5I, criticized by Hughes
in 'The Existence of a Legal System', 35 New York Universiry LR
(I96o ).
Page I 78. Mens rea and objective standards. See Holmes, 17ze Common
Law, Lecture I I; Hall, Principles qf Criminal Law, chaps. 5 and 6;
Hart, 'Legal Responsibility and Excuses', in Determinism and Freedom
(ed. Hook).
Page I 79路 Justification and excuse. On this distinction in the law of
homicide see Kenny, Outlines qf Criminal Law (24th edn.), pp. I09-
I6. For its general moral importance see Austin, 'A Plea for
Excuses', 57 PAS (I956-7); Hart, 'Prolegomenon to the Principles
ofPunishment', 6o PAS (I959-6o), p. I2. For a similar distinction
see Bentham, Of Laws in General, pp. I2I-2 on 'exemption' and
'exculpation'.
NOTES
Page I8I. Morality, human needs, and interests. For the view that the
criterion for calling a rule a moral rule is that it is the product of
reasoned and impartial consideration of the interests of those affected,
see Benn and Peters, Social Principles if the Democratic State, chap. 2.
Contrast Devlin, The Enforcement if Morals (I959).
CHAPTER IX
Page I 85. Natural Law. The existence of a vast literature of com
ment on classical, scholastic, and modern conceptions of Natural
Law and the ambiguities of the expression 'positivism' (see below)
often make it difficult to see precisely what issue is at stake when
Natural Law is opposed to Legal Positivism. An effort is made in
the text to identify one such issue. But very little can be gained | Clarendon |
from a discussion of this subject if only secondary sources are
read. Some first-hand acquaintance with the vocabulary and philo
sophical presuppositions of the primary sources is indispensable.
The following represent an easily accessible minimum. Aristotle,
Physics, ii, chap. 8 (trans. Ross, Oxford); Aquinas, Summa Theologica,
Quaestiones 90-7 (available with translation in D'Entreves, Aquinas:
Selected Political Writings, Oxford, I948); Grotius, On the Law if War
and Peace; Prolegomena (trans. in The Classics of International Law,
vol. 3, Oxford, I925); Blackstone, Commentaries, Introduction, s. 2.
Page I85. Legal Positivism. The expression 'positivism' is used in con
temporary Anglo-American literature to designate one or more of
the following contentions: (I) that laws are commands of human
beings; (2) that there is no necessary connection between law and
morals, or law as it is and law as it ought to be; (3) that the analysis
or study of meanings of legal concepts is an important study to be
distinguished from (though in no way hostile to) historical inquir
ies, sociological inquiries, and the critical appraisal of law in terms
of morals, social aims, functions, &c.; (4) that a legal system is a
'closed logical system' in which correct decisions can be deduced
from predetermined legal rules by logical means alone; (5) that
moral judgments cannot be established, as statements of fact can,
by rational argument, evidence or proof ('non cognitivism in eth
ics'). Bentham and Austin held the views expressed in (I), (2), and
(3) but not those in (4) and (5); Kelsen holds those expressed in
(2), (3), and (5) but not those in (I) or (4). Contention (4) is often
ascribed to 'analytical jurists' but apparently without good reason.
In continental literature the expression 'positivism' is often used
for the general repudiation of the claim that some principles or
rules of human conduct are discoverable by reason alone. See the
valuable discussion of the ambiguities of 'positivism' by Ago,
op. cit., in 51 American journal if International Law (I957).
NOTES
Page I86. Mill on Natural Law. See his Essay on Nature in Nature, the
Utility rif Religion and Theism.
Page I87. Blackstone and Bentham on Natural Law. Blackstone, loc. cit.,
and Bentham, Comment on the Commentaries, ss. I-6.
Page I93路 The minimum content rif natural law. This empirical version
of natural law is based on Hobbes, Leviathan, chaps. I4 and I 5, and
Hume, Treatise rif Human Nature, Book III, part 2; esp. ss. 2 and
4-7路
Page 200. Huckleberry Finn. Mark Twain's novel is a profound study
of the moral dilemma created by the existence of a social morality
which runs counter to the sympathies of an individual and to hu
manitarianism. It is a valuable corrective of the identification of all
morality with the latter.
Page 200. Slavery. For Aristotle a slave was 'a living instrument'.
(Politics, I, chaps. 2-4).
Page 203. The influence rif morality on law. Valuable studies of the ways
in which the development of law has been influenced by morality are
Ames, 'Law and Morals', 22 HLR (I9o8); Pound, Law and Morals
(I926); Goodhart, English Law and the Moral Law (I953). Austin fully
recognized this factual or causal connection. See The Province,
Lecture V, p. I62.
Page 204. Interpretation. On the place of moral considerations in the
interpretation of law see Lamont, The Value judgment, pp. 296-3 I;
Wechsler, 'Towards Neutral Principles of Constitutional Law', 73
HLR i, p. 96o; Hart, op. cit., in 71 HLR, pp. 6o6-I5, and Fuller's
criticism, ib. 66I ad fin. For Austin's recognition of the area left
open for judicial choice between 'competing analogies' and his criti | Clarendon |
cism of the judges' failure to adapt their decisions to the standard
of utility, see The Lectures, Lectures 37 and 38.
Page 205. Criticism rif law and the right rif all men to equal consideration.
See Benn and Peters, Social Principles and the Democratic State, chaps.
2 and 5, and Baier, The Moral Point rif View, chap. 8, for the view
that the recognition of such a right is not merely one among many
possible moralities but a defining feature of true morality.
Page 206. Principles of legality and justice. See Hall, Principles of
Criminal Law, chap. i and, for the 'internal morality oflaw', see Fuller,
op. cit., 71 HLR (1958), pp. 644-8.
Page 208. Revival of Natural Law doctrines in post-war Germany. See for
a discussion of the later views of G. Radbruch, Hart, and reply by
Fuller in op. cit. in 71 HLR (I958). The discussion there of the
decision of the Oberlandsgericht Bamberg of July I 949, in which a
NOTES
wife who had denounced her husband for an offence against a Nazi
statute of I934 was convicted of unlawfully depriving him of his
freedom, proceeded on the footing that the account of the case in 64
HLR (I95I), p. 1005, was correct and that the German court held
the statute of I934 to be invalid. The accuracy of this account has
recently been challenged by Pappe, 'On the Validity of Judicial
Decisions in the Nazi Era', 23 MLR (I96o). Dr Pappe's criticism is
well founded and the case as discussed by Hart should strictly be
regarded as hypothetical. As Dr Pappe shows (op. cit., p. 263), in
the actual case the court (Provincial Court of Appeal), after accept
ing the theoretical possibility that statutes might be unlawful if they
violated Natural Law, held that the Nazi statute in question did not
violate it; the accused was held guilty of an unlawful deprivation of
liberty since she had no duty to inform, but did so for purely per
sonal reasons and must have realized that to do so was in the
circumstances 'contrary to the sound conscience and sense of justice
of all decent human beings'. Dr Pappe's careful analysis of a deci
sion of the German Supreme Court in a similar case should be
studied (ib., p. 268 ad fin.).
CHAPTER X
Page 2I4. 'Is international law really law?' For the view that this is a
merely verbal question mistaken for a question of fact see Glanville
Williams, op. cit., in 22 BYBIL (I945).
Page 2 I 5路 Sources if doubt. For a constructive general survey see
A. H. Campbell, 'International Law and the Student of J urispru
dence' in 35 Grotius Society Proceedings (I95o); Gihl, 'The Legal
Character and Sources of International Law' in Scandinavian Studies
in Law (I957).
Page 2I6. 'How can international law be binding?' This question
(sometimes referred to as 'the problem of the binding force' of
international law) is raised by Fischer Williams, Chapters on Current
International Law, pp. I I-27; Brierly, The Law if Nations, 5th edn.
(I 955), chap. 2; The Basis if Obligation in International Law (I 958),
chap. r. See also Fitzmaurice, 'The Foundations of the Authority of
International Law and the Problem of Enforcement' in 19 MLR
(I956). These authors do not explicitly discuss the meaning of the
assertion that a system of rules is (or is not) binding.
Page 2I7. Sanctions in International Law. For the position under Art.
I 6 of the Covenant of the League of Nations see Fischer Williams,
'Sanctions under the Covenant' in 17 BYBIL (I936). For sanctions
under chapter vii of the UN Charter see Kelsen, 'Sanctions in
NOTES
International Law under the Charter of U.N.', 31 Iowa LR (I946),
and Tucker, 'The Interpretation of War under present Interna
tional Law', 4 The International Law Quarterly (I 95 I). On the Korean | Clarendon |
War, see Stone, Legal Controls if International Coriflict (I954), chap. ix,
Discourse I4. It is of course arguable that the Uniting for Peace
Resolution showed that the United Nations was not 'paralyzed'.
Page 220. International Law thought and spoken if as obligatory. See Jessup,
A Modern Law if Nations, chap. I, and 'The Reality of International
Law', IIB Foreign Affairs (I940).
Page 220. The Sovereignty, if States. For a clear exposition of the view
that 'sovereignty is only a name given to so much of the interna
tional field as is left by law to the individual action of states' see
Fischer Williams, op. cit., pp. ID-II, 285-99, and Aspects if Modern
International Law, pp. 24-6, and Van Kleffens, 'Sovereignty and
International Law', Recueil des Cours (I 953), i, pp. 82-3.
Page 221. The State. For the notion of a 'state' and types of depend
ent states see Brierly, The Law if Nations, chap. 4路
Page 224. Voluntarist and 'Auto-limitation' theories. The principal au
thors are J ellinek, Die Rechtliche Natur der Staatsvertriige; Triepel, 'Les
Rapports entre le droit interne et la droit internationale', Recueil des
Cours (I923). The extreme view is that of Zorn, Grund;::iige des
Volkerrechts. See the critical discussion of this form of 'positivism' in
Gihl, op. cit., in Scandinavian Studies in Law (I957); Starke, An In
troduction to International Law, chap. I; Fischer Williams, Chapters on
Current International Law, pp. I I-I 6.
Page 224. Obligation and consent. The view that no rule of interna
tional law is binding on a state without its prior consent, express or
tacit, has been expressed by English courts (seeR. v. Keyn I876, 2
Ex. Div. 63, 'The Franconia') and also by the Permanent Court of
International Justice. See The Lotus, PCI] Series A, No. IO.
Page 226. New States and States acquiring maritime territory. See Kelsen,
Principles if International Law, pp. 3 I 2- I 3路
Page 226. Effect on non-parties if general international treaties. See Kelsen,
op. cit., 345 ff.; Starke, op. cit., chap. I; Brierly, op. cit., chap. vii,
pp. 25I-2.
Page 227. Comprehensive use if term 'morality'. See Austin on 'positive
morality' in The Province, Lecture V, pp. I25-9, I4I-2.
Page 230. Moral obligation to obey international law. For the view that
this is 'the foundation' of international law see Lauterpacht, Intro
duction to Brierly's The Base if Obligation in International Law, xviii,
and Brierly, ib., chap. 1.
306
NOTES
Page 232. Treaty imposed by force as legislation. See Scott, 'The Legal
Nature of International Law' in American journal !if International Law
(I907) at pp. 837, 862-4. For criticism of the common description
of general treaties as 'international legislation' see Jennings, 'The
Progressive Development of International Law and its Codifica
tion', 24 BYBIL (I947) at p. 303.
Page 233路 Decentralized sanctions. See Kelsen, op. cit., p. 20, and
Tucker in op. cit., 4 International Law Quarterly (I 95 I).
Page 233. The basic norm !if international law. For its formulation as
pacta sunt servanda see Anzilotti, Corso di diritto interna;::,ionale (I923), p.
40. For the substitution of 'States ought to behave as they have
customarily behaved' see Kelsen, General Theory, p. 369, and Prin
ciples !if International Law, p. 4I8. See the important critical discus
sion by Gihl, International Legislation (I937) and op. cit. in Scandinavian
Studies in Law (I957), pp. 62 ff. For the fuller development of the
interpretation of international law as containing no basic norm see
Ago, 'Positive Law and International Law' in 51 American Journal !if
International Law (I 95 7) and Scien;::,a giuridica e diritto interna;::,ionale | Clarendon |
(I958). Gihl draws the conclusion that in spite of Article 38 of the
Statute of the International Court international law has no formal
sources of law. See for an attempt to formulate for international law
an 'initial hypothesis' which seems open to similar criticisms to
those urged in the text, Lauterpacht, The Future !if Law in the Inter
national Community, pp. 420-3.
Page 237. Analogy !if content between international law and municipal law.
See Campbell, op. cit. in 35 Grotius Society Proceedings (I 950), p. I 2 I
ad fin., and the discussion of treaties and the rules governing acqui
sition of territory, prescriptions, leases, mandates, servitudes, &c.,
in Lauterpacht, Private Law Sources and Analogies !if International Law
(I927).
Page 272. [An alternative beginning to this section is included here,
as it was not discarded.)
Throughout the long sequence of his writings on adjudication
Dworkin has unswervingly maintained his denial that the courts
have discretion in the sense of a law-creating power to decide
cases left incompletely regulated by the existing law. Indeed he
has argued that apart from some trivial exceptions there are no
such cases, since as he has famously said, there is always a single
'right answer' to any meaningful question as to what the law is
on any point of law arising in any case.'
' [See his 'No Right Answer?' in P.M. S. Hacker andJ. Raz (eds.), Law, Morality
and Society ( 1977), pp. 58-84; reprinted with revisions as 'Is There Really No Right
Answer in Hard Cases?' AMP, chap. 5.]
NOTES
But notwithstanding this appearance of an unchanging doc
trine, Dworkin's later introduction of interpretive ideas into
his legal theory and his claim that all propositions of law are
'interpretive' in the special sense which he has given to this
expression, has (as Raz was the first to make clear)" brought the
substance of this position very close to my own in recognizing
that the courts in fact have and frequently exercise a law-creating
discretion. Arguably before the introduction of interpretive ideas
into his theory there seemed to be a great difference between our
respective accounts of adjudication, because Dworkin's earlier
denial of judicial discretion in the strong sense and his insistence
that there is always a right answer were associated with the idea
that the judge's role in deciding cases was to discern and enforce
existing law. But this earlier conception which of course conflicted
very sharply with my claim that the courts in deciding cases often
exercise a law-creating discretion does not figure at all in
[The text of the alternative beginning to Section 6 ends at this
point.]
' [SeeJ. Raz. 'Dworkin: A New Link in the Chain', 74 California Law Review, I 103
(1g86) at IIIO, IIIS-16.)
INDEX
(N.B. References to pages after p. 276 are to the Notes)
Adjudication, rules of, 96-99;
theory of 259, 275; and see
Courts, Judges.
Agnelli, A., 283.
Ago, 293, 302, 306.
Allen, C. K., 294路
Ames, J. B., 303.
Analogy, I6, 8I, 274,280,306.
Anzilotti, D., 306.
Aquinas, 8n., I9I, 302.
Aristotle, I62, I9I, 28o, 300,
302, 303.
Atkin, Lord, 264.
Augustine, St., 8n., I4, I56.
Austin, John, I, 6, 7, 8, I 6,
I7, I8, I9, 20, 2In., 23,
25, 60, 63, 73, 74, 8I, I49,
207, 2II, 244, 246, 277,
278, 280, 28I, 282, 283,
285, 286, 287, 288, 289,
290, 299, 300, 30 I, 302,
303, 305.
Austin, J. L., I4, 279, 301.
Authority, I 9-20, 98;
legislative, 58-64, 70.
distinguished from power,
63, 20I, 202-3.
Baier, K., 287, 292, 303.
Basic Norm, see Kelsen, H.,
and Recognition, Rule of.
Bohnert, H. G., 280.
Bradley, F. H., 301.
Brierly, J. L., 304, 305.
Broad, C. D., 291.
Buckland, W. W., 284, 286.
| Clarendon |
Campbell, A. H., 286, 290,
304, 306.
Cardozo, B., 274.
Cattaneo, M., 296.
Certainty of Law, see
Uncertainty.
Change, rule of, 95-9; and see
Legislation.
Cohen, L. J., 279, 291.
Cohen, M., 242.
Coleman, J ., 25 I, 265.
Commands, I6, I9-2o; and see
Imperatives; Orders; Tacit
commands.
Commonwealth, emergence of
independent legal systems
in, I 20-2, 296; and see
Constitutional Law;
Westminster, Statute of.
Conceptualism, I 23, I 29-30,
297; and see Formalism.
Constitutional Law:
as 'positive morality', I.
restricting legislature, 68-70,
7I-8, 289-90.
Benn, S. I., and Peters, R. S.,
amendment of, 72-3, n-8,
300, 302, 303.
Bentham, Jeremy, I7, 63,
I87, 2I I, 237, 244, 272,
279, 28 I, 286, 287, 289,
290, 30I, 302, 303.
Blackstone, I87, 302, 303.
290.
And see Legislature;
Limitations, Legal;
Parliament; Recognition,
Rule of; South Africa;
United States.
310
INDEX
Contracts, 9, 28, 38, 4I, 96;
Duties, 7, 27-8, 4I-2, I70-I,
and see Promises.
Conventions of British
Constitution, I I I, 295路
Courts, 2, 5, 29-30, 40, 97,
I36, I37路
and rule of recognition, 6s-6,
II3-I7, I48-9, IS2-4.
creative function of, I 32-6,
I4I-7' 272, 273-6.
finality and infallibility of,
I4I-7.
268-9, 271.
distinguished from disability,
69-70.
character of rules imposing,
87, 256.
and obligation, 284.
and predictions, 286.
And see Obligation; Rules.
Dworkin, R. M., 238-76,
306-7.
And see Adjudication; Judges;
Efficacy of Law, 103-4,
Precedent; Realism.
Cowen, D. V ., 299路
Criminal Law, 6-7, 9, 24, 27,
28, 32, 33, 37, 40-I, 79,
87.
Cross, R., 298.
Custom, legal status of, 44-8,
64, 68, 9I, 287, 29I, 292;
and see Rules, Primary;
Tacit Command.
Daube, D., 283.
Definition, I3-I7: of law, 6,
208-I2, 2I3-IS, 239-40,
279路
Del Vecchio, G., 299路
Democracy:
judges in a, 275路
legislators in a, 6o.
sovereign in a, so, 73-6.
Devlin, L.J ., 302.
Dewey, J ., 297.
Diamond, A. S., 291.
Dicey, A. V., III, ISI, 295路
Dickinson, J ., 29 I, 297, 298.
Discretion:
of rule-making bodies, I 32.
of Courts, I4I-7, 252, 254,
259, 272-3, 275-6.
of scorer in a game, I42-6.
Dixon, Sir 0., 296, 299路
294-5路
Electorate as sovereign, 48,
7I-8, 290.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E., 292.
Existence:
of a legal system, 6o-I,
I I 2-I 7, 295-6.
of a rule, I09-IO.
Fiction involved in rules, I 2.
Fitzmaurice, G. G., 304.
Formalism, I 24-54, 297; and
see Conceptualism.
Frank, Jerome, 277, 286, 289,
291.
Frankfurter, F., 290.
Friedmann, W ., 299, 300.
Fuller, L. L., 208n., 238,
303.
Games:
variety of rules in, 9, 3 I.
scoring rule in, 34, 59, I 02.
theory that all rules are
addressed to officials
applied to, 40, 285.
internal aspect of rules in,
s6-7.
persistence of law illustrated
by umpire's decision in,
63.
INDEX
311
move in chess and
compliance with rules in,
I40-I.
scorer's discretion in and
theory that law is what
Courts do, I42-5.
definition of, 280.
Gavison, R., 238, 240.
Germany:
Nazi, 200, 208.
revival of natural law
arguments in post-war,
208-I 2, 303-4.
Gihl, T., 304, 305, 306.
Gluckman, M., 292.
Goodhart, A. L., 296, 303.
Gray, J. C., I, I4I, 207, 278,
287, 289.
Grice, P., 281.
Grotius, 302.
Habits and rules, 9-I 2,
55-60, 289; and see
Obedience; Rules.
Hagerstrom, A., 279, 28I,
287, 291.
Hall, J ., 303.
Hand, Learned, 298.
Hare, R. M., 280, 287.
Hart, H. L. A., !.W8n. I, 279,
28I, 282, 285, 289, 290,
29 I, 295, 296, 297, 299,
30I, 303, 304. [See also
238 ff.]
Hoadly, Bishop, I4I, I45路
Hobbes, T., 63, I9I, 289,
299-300, 303.
Hofstadter, A., and
McKinvey, J. C. C., 28o.
Hohfeld, W. N ., 289.
Holmes, 0. W., J., I, 8, 274,
278, 286, 290, 298, 30!.
Huckleberry Finn, 200, 303.
Hughes, C. E., C. J., 298-9.
Hughes, G., 295, 301.
Honore, A. M., 297. | Clarendon |
Hume, D., I9I, 303.
Hutcheson, J. C., 298.
Imperatives, varieties of, I 8-20,
280-I; and see Commands;
Orders; Tacit Command.
Independence:
of a legal system, 24, 25,
I I9-22, 296.
of a state, 22I-6.
Internal and External Points
of View, 89-9I, 242-3,
254; and see Rules, internal
aspect o拢
International Law, 3, 4, 68,
79, II9, I22, I56, I77'
I95, I98, 2I3-37, 304-6.
Interpretation, 204-5, 263-8.
Iraq, 226.
Israel, 226.
Jackson, H., 300.
Jellinek., G., 305.
Jenks, E., 284.
Jennings, R., 306.
Jennings, W. lvor, 289.
Jensen, 0. C., 297路
Jessup, P. C., 305.
Jones, J. W., 297.
Judges:
powers of, 29, 4 I, 96-7.
duties of, 29.
phenomenology of decision-
making by, 273-4.
And see Courts.
Jurisdiction, 29-30, 36, 97-8;
and see Courts.
Justice, 7-8, I55-67, 246,
299-300.
in distribution, I 58-64, I 67.
in compensation, I 63-6.
natural, I 6o, 206.
312
INDEX
Kant, I., go 1.
Kantorowicz, H., 279, 2g8,
go I.
dependence on language of,
I24-8.
and morality, I76-8,
Kelsen, H., 2, I8, g5-6, 207,
22g-go.
2gg, 278, 28g, 284, 286,
287, 292-g, 294-5, 296-7,
go2, go4, go5, go6; and see
Recognition, Rule of.
Lamont, W. D., gog.
Latham, R. T., 2g6.
Lauterpacht, H., go5, go6.
League of Nations, 2 I 7.
Legal System:
existence of, 6I, I I2-I7,
295路
distinguished from a set of
separate rules, g2-g,
2g4-7, 249路
interruption of, I I 8-I g.
emergence of new, I 20-1.
partial breakdown of, I 22-g.
And see Revolution.
Legal Theory, v-vi, I-2,
I6-I7.
as descriptive, v, 240, 242-4.
as general, 2gg-4o, 242,
244路
as evaluative and interpretive,
240-4, 248-g, 26g, 271.
as semantic, 244-8.
imperative, vi, 244, and see
Orders.
And see Natural Law;
Positivism, Legal,
Realism, Legal.
and international law,
22g-gi, 2g2-g, go5.
Legislature, 5, 48, 275, 282-g;
and see Legislation;
Sovereign.
Limitations, legal on
legislature, 66-7 I, 73, 7 4,
77 , 106.
Lyons, D., 265.
Macmillan, Lord, 274路
Marshall, G., 279, 28g, 295,
2g6, 297' 299路
Melden, A., 282, 285, 2go,
go I.
Mill, J. S., I 86, I 87, gog.
Miller, 2g8.
Montesquieu, I 86, I 87.
Moore, M., 241.
Morality:
and law, 7-8, I 7, 86,
I85-2I 2, 268-72.
characterization of, I 55-84,
227-go, go1.
obligations of, I 6g-82.
'internality' of, I 72-g,
I7g-8o.
importance of, I 73-5.
immunity of from deliberate
change, I 7 5-8.
and voluntary action, I 78-g.
social pressure supporting,
Legislation, 22, go-gi, g8,
I7g-8o.
282-g, 286-7.
self-binding, 42-4, 286-7.
authority of, 54-5路 58-6g,
288-g.
legal limits on, 66-7 I.
manner and form of, 68, 7 I,
I50-2, 28g.
ideals of, I82-g.
personal forms of, I 84.
and human interests, I 80-2.
and criticism of law, I55-67,
I8g-4, 205-6.
and legal validity, 200-I 2,
25g-4.
INDEX
and development of law,
2og-4, gog.
and international law,
227-g2.
And see Natural Law.
Morison, W. L., 28g, 287,
288.
Natural Justice, I6o, 206.
Natural Law, 8, I56, I8I,
I85-2oo, go2, gog.
concept of nature in,
I88-gi.
empirical version of, Igi-g.
minimum content of,
Igg-200.
revival of in post-war
Germany, 2o8-I2, gog-4.
Negligence, Ig2-g.
Normative language, 57, 86,
I I 7; and see Obligation;
Rules.
Nowell-Smith, P., 290.
Nuer, The, 292.
Nullity, 28, go-I, gg-s, 49,
285, 286.
Obedience, Ig, go, gi-2.
habit of, 24, so-66, 75,
76-7.
and continuity of legislative
authority, SI-61.
and persistence of laws,
6I-6.
and existence of a legal
system, I I 2- I 7. And see
Habits and rules.
Obligation, 6-7, 27, 4g-4,
82-gi, 284.
analysis of in terms of rules,
82-gi, 2go.
and feelings of compulsion,
88, I g8, 290.
and prediction of sanction,
Io-I I, 8g-5, 88-gi,
Ig7-9路
having an, distinguished
from being obliged, 82-g,
go, 282.
moral and legal, I 67-70.
in international law, 2I6-26.
and duty, 284.
| Clarendon |
Officials, 20-I, g8-g, 6o-I,
go-8, I Ig-I7.
Olivecrona, K., 278.
Open texture of law, I2g,
I28-g6, I45, I47, 204,
252, 272-g, 278, 297路
Orders:
backed by threats or
coercive, 6, I6, Ig, 20-5.
and rules conferring powers,
28-g2.
and legislation, 42.
inadequacy of for analysis of
law, 48-g, 79-80.
And see Imperatives;
Commands; Tacit
Command; Rules.
Pappe, H., go4.
Parliament, 25, I07.
sovereignty of, 67, 74-8,
I07, III, I49-52, 282-g,
299路
and Commonwealth, I 20- I,
2g6.
Parliament Acts 1911 and
1949路 ISI-2.
Payne, D. J., 287.
Perelman, Ch., 299.
Piddington, R., 28g.
Plato, I62, I86.
Positivism, legal, 8, I 85-6,
207, 2I2, 24I, 244-54,
259, 265, 268, 269-70,
27 I, 272, go2.
INDEX
Pound, R., 297, 303.
Powers, see Rules, conferring
powers.
Precedent, I 24-6, I 27, I 34-5,
I 54, 297, 298.
conferring powers
distinguished from rules
imposing obligations or
duties, 26-49, 8o-I, 283-6.
contrasted with habits, 9-I I,
Primitive law, 3, 4, 84, 9I-2,
ss-6o, 289.
IS6, 291.
Promises, 34, 43-4, I97,
225-6.
Prosser, W. L., 300.
Punishment, 7, I o- I I , 27, 34,
36-7, 39, 89, I73, I79-8o;
and see Sanction; Criminal
Law.
Radbruch, G., 303.
Radcliffe, Lord, 277.
Raphael, D., 300.
Rawls, J ., 246, 300.
Raz, J ., 254, 262.
Realism, legal, 65, I36-47,
289, 298; and see Courts,
Rules.
Recognition, Rule of, 94-5,
96-9, IOO-IO, 246, 247,
250, 2SI-2, 256, 258, 259,
263-6, 268, 292-3, 294>
295路
uncertainty of, I 22, I 23,
I47-54, 251.
and Courts, I I s-I 7' 267.
in international law, 233-6,
306.
And see Kelsen; Validity.
Reid, Lord, 274路
Revolution, 1 I 8-20, 296.
Rights, 7, 54-5, s8-9, 88,
268-9, 27I-2.
Robinson, R., 279.
Ross, A., 280, 284, 286, 290,
295, 299路
Rules:
varieties of, 8-IO, 27-33,
I70-2.
internal aspect of, s6-7'
88-90, 99, Io2-3, 104,
I08, IIS-I6, II7, 20I,
242, 255> 289, 291.
'practice theory of' 254-9.
scepticism as to existence of,
I 2-I 3, I 24-54路
and obligations, 85-91.
and predictions, I37-47路
different social functions of,
38-42, 284-5路
acceptance of, 55-6 I,
II3-I7, 255, 257路
primary, regime of, 9I-4.
law as combination of
primary and secondary,
79-99, I I7, 2I3, 249-50.
distinguished from variable
standards, I3I-4, 263,
297-8.
connexion with justice,
I60-I, 206-7.
and difference between
'convention' and
'conviction', 255-6, 266.
normative character of,
256-7.
and principles, 259-68.
And see Recognition, Rule of;
Normative language.
Ryle, G., 279.
Salmond, J., 284, 292, 294.
Sanction, 27, 33-5, 36-8, 48,
98, I98-200, 2I6-20,
29I-2, 304-5, 306; and see
Nullity; Orders.
Sankey, Lord, I52.
INDEX
Scandinavian legal theory,
Uncertainty:
IO, 278; and see Hagerstrom,
Olivecrona; Ross.
Schulz, F., 292.
Scott, J. B., 306.
Sidgwick, H., 288, 289, 299路
Soper, E., 25I, 265.
Sources of Law, 95, 97, IOI,
106, 264-7, 269, 294; and
see Recognition, Rule of;
Statutes as merely sources
of law; Validity.
South Africa, constitutional
problems in, 7I-3, I22-3,
I53, 200, 297, 299路
Sovereign, 25, so-78, I48-s2,
223-6, 287-9路
of legal rules, I 2, I 24-33,
I47-s4, 25I-2, 272-3.
of precedent, I 25, I 34-5.
And see Open texture.
United Nations Charter, 2I7,
233, 304-5路
United States of America,
constitution of, I 3, 36, 72,
73, 74, 78, 106, I45, 250,
26 I, 264, 290.
Urmson, J. 0., 301.
Validity, Legal, 69, 98-9,
IOO-IO, 200, 247, 250,
25I, 253, 254, 294-5路
of morally iniquitous rules,
Sovereignty of States, 220-6,
207-I 2, 268.
305.
State, so, 53, 98, I95, 220-6,
305, 306.
Statutes as merely sources of
law, 2, 64-6, I37路
Statute of Westminster, I52,
299路
Starke, J. G., 305.
Stone, J., 287, 297, 305.
Strawson, P. F., 301.
Strict liability, I66, 173, I78-9.
Switzerland, constitution of,
72, 290.
| Clarendon |
And see Recognition, Rule o拢
Van Kleffens, E. N., 305.
Wade, H. W. R., 295, 299.
Waismann, F., 297路
Waluchow, W. J., 262.
Warren, S. D., and Brandeis,
L. D., 300.
Wechsler, H., 303.
Wedberg, A., 291.
Wheare, K. C., 289, 295, 296,
299路
Wills, 9, I 2, 28, 30, 34, 36-8,
4I, 96.
Tacit command or order,
Williams, Glanville L., 278,
44-5, 63-5, n-8, 8o, 226,
287, 289.
Taxes contrasted with
punishment, 39路
Tort, laws of, 27, 300.
Triepel, H., 305.
Tucker, R. W., 305, 306.
Twain, Mark, 303.
279, 300, 304.
Williams, J. F., 304, 305.
Winch, P ., 289, 297.
Wisdom, J ., 277, 278.
Wittgenstein, L., 280, 297.
Wollheim, R., 279.
Zorn, P ., 305.
| Clarendon |