human
stringlengths 301
5k
|
---|
If quaternions, of which I have just spoken, had not been so
promptly utilized by the English physicists, many persons would
doubtless see in them only a useless fancy, and yet, in teaching us
to liken what appearances separate, they would have already
rendered us more apt to penetrate the secrets of nature. |
When Newton's law has been substituted for Kepler's we still
know only elliptic motion. Now, in so far as concerns this motion,
the two laws differ only in form; we pass from one to the other
by a simple differentiation. And yet from Newton's law may be
deduced by an immediate generalization all the effects of perturbations
and the whole of celestial mechanics. If, on the other
hand, Kepler's enunciation had been retained, no one would ever
have regarded the orbits of the perturbed planets, those complicated
curves of which no one has ever written the equation, as
the natural generalizations of the ellipse. The progress of observations
would only have served to create belief in chaos. |
It was because Maxwell was accustomed to 'think in vectors,'
and yet it was through the theory of imaginaries (neomonics)
that vectors were introduced into analysis. And those who invented
imaginaries hardly suspected the advantage which would
be obtained from them for the study of the real world, of this the
name given them is proof sufficient. |
To sum up, the aim of mathematical physics is not only to
facilitate for the physicist the numerical calculation of certain
constants or the integration of certain differential equations. It
is besides, it is above all, to reveal to him the hidden harmony of
things in making him see them in a new way. |
The combinations which numbers and symbols may form are an
infinite multitude. In this multitude how shall we choose those
which are worthy to fix our attention? Shall we let ourselves be
guided solely by our caprice? This caprice, which itself would
besides soon tire, would doubtless carry us very far apart and we
should quickly cease to understand each other. |
History proves that physics has not only forced us to choose
among problems which came in a crowd; it has imposed upon us
such as we should without it never have dreamed of. However
varied may be the imagination of man, nature is still a thousand
times richer. To follow her we must take ways we have
neglected, and these paths lead us often to summits whence we
discover new countries. What could be more useful! |
The sole natural object of mathematical thought is the whole
number. It is the external world which has imposed the continuum
upon us, which we doubtless have invented, but which it
has forced us to invent. Without it there would be no infinitesimal
analysis; all mathematical science would reduce itself to
arithmetic or to the theory of substitutions. |
On the contrary, we have devoted to the study of the continuum
almost all our time and all our strength. Who will regret
it; who will think that this time and this strength have been
wasted? Analysis unfolds before us infinite perspectives that
arithmetic never suspects; it shows us at a glance a majestic
assemblage whose array is simple and symmetric; on the contrary,
in the theory of numbers, where reigns the unforeseen, the
view is, so to speak, arrested at every step. |
Fourier's series is a precious instrument of which analysis
makes continual use, it is by this means that it has been able to
represent discontinuous functions; Fourier invented it to solve a
problem of physics relative to the propagation of heat. If this
problem had not come up naturally, we should never have dared
to give discontinuity its rights; we should still long have regarded
continuous functions as the only true functions. |
The notion of function has been thereby considerably extended
and has received from some logician-analysts an unforeseen development.
These analysts have thus adventured into regions
where reigns the purest abstraction and have gone as far away
as possible from the real world. Yet it is a problem of physics
which has furnished them the occasion. |
The theory of partial differential equations of the second
order has an analogous history. It has been developed chiefly
by and for physics. But it may take many forms, because such
an equation does not suffice to determine the unknown function,
it is necessary to adjoin to it complementary conditions which
are called conditions at the limits; whence many different
problems. |
If the analysts had abandoned themselves to their natural tendencies,
they would never have known but one, that which
Madame Kovalevski has treated in her celebrated memoir. But
there are a multitude of others which they would have ignored.
Each of the theories of physics, that of electricity, that of heat,
presents us these equations under a new aspect. It may, therefore,
be said that without these theories we should not know
partial differential equations. |
In this way, in the study of functions of complex variables, the
analyst, alongside of the geometric image, which is his usual instrument,
finds many physical images which he may make
use of with the same success. Thanks to these images, he can
see at a glance what pure deduction would show him only successively.
He masses thus the separate elements of the solution,
and by a sort of intuition divines before being able to
demonstrate. |
It is true, the arguments of this species are not rigorous, in
the sense the analyst attaches to this word. And here a question
arises: How can a demonstration not sufficiently rigorous for
the analyst suffice for the physicist? It seems there can not be
two rigors, that rigor is or is not, and that, where it is not there
can not be deduction. |
Now the numbers the physicist measures by experiment are
never known except approximately; and besides, any function
always differs as little as you choose from a discontinuous function,
and at the same time it differs as little as you choose from
a continuous function. The physicist may, therefore, at will
suppose that the function studied is continuous, or that it is discontinuous;
that it has or has not a derivative; and may do so
without fear of ever being contradicted, either by present experience
or by any future experiment. We see that with such
liberty he makes sport of difficulties which stop the analyst. He
may always reason as if all the functions which occur in his
calculations were entire polynomials. |
Thus the sketch which suffices for physics is not the deduction
which analysis requires. It does not follow thence that one
can not aid in finding the other. So many physical sketches have
already been transformed into rigorous demonstrations that
to-day this transformation is easy. There would be plenty of
examples did I not fear in citing them to tire the reader. |
Governments and parliaments must find that astronomy is one
of the sciences which cost most dear: the least instrument costs
hundreds of thousands of dollars, the least observatory costs
millions; each eclipse carries with it supplementary appropriations.
And all that for stars which are so far away, which are
complete strangers to our electoral contests, and in all probability
will never take any part in them. It must be that our politicians
have retained a remnant of idealism, a vague instinct for
what is grand; truly, I think they have been calumniated; they
should be encouraged and shown that this instinct does not deceive
them, that they are not dupes of that idealism. |
Astronomy is useful because it raises us above ourselves; it is
useful because it is grand; that is what we should say. It shows
us how small is man's body, how great his mind, since his intelligence
can embrace the whole of this dazzling immensity, where
his body is only an obscure point, and enjoy its silent harmony.
Thus we attain the consciousness of our power, and this is something
which can not cost too dear, since this consciousness makes
us mightier. |
The stars send us not only that visible and gross light which
strikes our bodily eyes, but from them also comes to us a light far
more subtle, which illuminates our minds and whose effects I
shall try to show you. You know what man was on the earth
some thousands of years ago, and what he is to-day. Isolated
amidst a nature where everything was a mystery to him, terrified
at each unexpected manifestation of incomprehensible forces, he
was incapable of seeing in the conduct of the universe anything
but caprice; he attributed all phenomena to the action of a multitude
of little genii, fantastic and exacting, and to act on the
world he sought to conciliate them by means analogous to those
employed to gain the good graces of a minister or a deputy.
Even his failures did not enlighten him, any more than to-day
a beggar refused is discouraged to the point of ceasing to beg. |
To-day we no longer beg of nature; we command her, because
we have discovered certain of her secrets and shall discover
others each day. We command her in the name of laws she can
not challenge, because they are hers; these laws we do not madly
ask her to change, we are the first to submit to them. Nature
can only be governed by obeying her. |
What a change must our souls have undergone to pass from the
one state to the other! Does any one believe that, without the
lessons of the stars, under the heavens perpetually overclouded
that I have just supposed, they would have changed so quickly?
Would the metamorphosis have been possible, or at least would it
not have been much slower? |
And then, taught by this example, we have seen our little terrestrial
world better and, under the apparent disorder, there also
we have found again the harmony that the study of the heavens
had revealed to us. It also is regular, it also obeys immutable
laws, but they are more complicated, in apparent conflict one with
another, and an eye untrained by other sights would have seen
there only chaos and the reign of chance or caprice. If we had
not known the stars, some bold spirits might perhaps have
sought to foresee physical phenomena; but their failures would
have been frequent, and they would have excited only the derision
of the vulgar; do we not see, that even in our day the
meteorologists sometimes deceive themselves, and that certain
persons are inclined to laugh at them. |
How often would the physicists, disheartened by so many
checks, have fallen into discouragement, if they had not had, to
sustain their confidence, the brilliant example of the success of
the astronomers! This success showed them that nature obeys
laws; it only remained to know what laws; for that they only
needed patience, and they had the right to demand that the
sceptics should give them credit. |
But are these laws not local, varying in different places, like
those which men make; does not that which is truth in one corner
of the universe, on our globe, for instance, or in our little solar
system, become error a little farther away? And then could it
not be asked whether laws depending on space do not also depend
upon time, whether they are not simple habitudes, transitory,
therefore, and ephemeral? Again it is astronomy that answers
this question. Consider the double stars; all describe conics;
thus, as far as the telescope carries, it does not reach the limits
of the domain which obeys Newton's law. |
Even the simplicity of this law is a lesson for us; how many
complicated phenomena are contained in the two lines of its
enunciation; persons who do not understand celestial mechanics
may form some idea of it at least from the size of the treatises
devoted to this science; and then it may be hoped that the complication
of physical phenomena likewise hides from us some
simple cause still unknown. |
How was the order of the universe understood by the
ancients; for instance, by Pythagoras, Plato or Aristotle? It
was either an immutable type fixed once for all, or an ideal to
which the world sought to approach. Kepler himself still
thought thus when, for instance, he sought whether the distances
of the planets from the sun had not some relation to the five regular
polyhedrons. This idea contained nothing absurd, but it
was sterile, since nature is not so made. Newton has shown us
that a law is only a necessary relation between the present state
of the world and its immediately subsequent state. All the
other laws since discovered are nothing else; they are in sum,
differential equations; but it is astronomy which furnished the
first model for them, without which we should doubtless long
have erred. |
The ancients thought everything was made for man, and this
illusion must be very tenacious, since it must ever be combated.
Yet it is necessary to divest oneself of it; or else one will be only
an eternal myope, incapable of seeing the truth. To comprehend
nature one must be able to get out of self, so to speak, and to
contemplate her from many different points of view; otherwise
we never shall know more than one side. Now, to get out of
self is what he who refers everything to himself can not do. Who
delivered us from this illusion? It was those who showed us that
the earth is only one of the smallest planets of the solar system,
and that the solar system itself is only an imperceptible point
in the infinite spaces of the stellar universe. |
Was I wrong in saying that it is astronomy which has made
us a soul capable of comprehending nature; that under heavens
always overcast and starless, the earth itself would have been for
us eternally unintelligible; that we should there have seen only
caprice and disorder; and that, not knowing the world, we should
never have been able to subdue it? What science could have
been more useful? And in thus speaking I put myself at the
point of view of those who only value practical applications.
Certainly, this point of view is not mine; as for me, on the contrary,
if I admire the conquests of industry, it is above all because
if they free us from material cares, they will one day give
to all the leisure to contemplate nature. I do not say: Science
is useful, because it teaches us to construct machines. I say:
Machines are useful, because in working for us, they will some
day leave us more time to make science. But finally it is worth
remarking that between the two points of view there is no antagonism,
and that man having pursued a disinterested aim, all else
has been added unto him. |
Auguste Comte has said somewhere, that it would be idle to
seek to know the composition of the sun, since this knowledge
would be of no use to sociology. How could he be so short-sighted?
Have we not just seen that it is by astronomy that, to
speak his language, humanity has passed from the theological to
the positive state? He found an explanation for that because
it had happened. But how has he not understood that what
remained to do was not less considerable and would be not less
profitable? Physical astronomy, which he seems to condemn,
has already begun to bear fruit, and it will give us much more,
for it only dates from yesterday. |
But, it will be said, astronomy has given to the other sciences
all it can give them, and now that the heavens have procured for
us the instruments which enable us to study terrestrial nature,
they could without danger veil themselves forever. After what
we have just said, is there still need to answer this objection?
One could have reasoned the same in Ptolemy's time; then also
men thought they knew everything, and they still had almost
everything to learn. |
The stars are majestic laboratories, gigantic crucibles, such as
no chemist could dream. There reign temperatures impossible
for us to realize. Their only defect is being a little far away;
but the telescope will soon bring them near to us, and then we
shall see how matter acts there. What good fortune for the
physicist and the chemist! |
If it is easy to propound them: to answer is difficult. If we
felt tempted to risk a prediction, we should easily resist this
temptation, by thinking of all the stupidities the most eminent
savants of a hundred years ago would have uttered, if some one
had asked them what the science of the nineteenth century
would be. They would have thought themselves bold in their
predictions, and after the event, how very timid we should have
found them. Do not, therefore, expect of me any prophecy. |
But if, like all prudent physicians, I shun giving a prognosis,
yet I can not dispense with a little diagnostic; well, yes, there are
indications of a serious crisis, as if we might expect an approaching
transformation. Still, be not too anxious: we are sure the
patient will not die of it, and we may even hope that this crisis
will be salutary, for the history of the past seems to guarantee us
this. This crisis, in fact, is not the first, and to understand it,
it is important to recall those which have preceded. Pardon then
a brief historical sketch. |
The astronomic universe is formed of masses, very great, no
doubt, but separated by intervals so immense that they appear
to us only as material points. These points attract each other
inversely as the square of the distance, and this attraction is the
sole force which influences their movements. But if our senses
were sufficiently keen to show us all the details of the bodies
which the physicist studies, the spectacle thus disclosed would
scarcely differ from the one the astronomer contemplates. There
also we should see material points, separated from one another
by intervals, enormous in comparison with their dimensions, and
describing orbits according to regular laws. These infinitesimal
stars are the atoms. Like the stars proper, they attract or repel
each other, and this attraction or this repulsion, following the
straight line which joins them, depends only on the distance.
The law according to which this force varies as function of the
distance is perhaps not the law of Newton, but it is an analogous
law; in place of the exponent −2, we have probably a different
exponent, and it is from this change of exponent that arises all
the diversity of physical phenomena, the variety of qualities and
of sensations, all the world, colored and sonorous, which surrounds
us; in a word, all nature. |
Such is the primitive conception in all its purity. It only
remains to seek in the different cases what value should be given
to this exponent in order to explain all the facts. It is on this
model that Laplace, for example, constructed his beautiful theory
of capillarity; he regards it only as a particular case of attraction,
or, as he says, of universal gravitation, and no one is astonished
to find it in the middle of one of the five volumes of the
'Mécanique céleste.' More recently Briot believes he penetrated
the final secret of optics in demonstrating that the atoms of ether
attract each other in the inverse ratio of the sixth power of the
distance; and Maxwell himself, does he not say somewhere that
the atoms of gases repel each other in the inverse ratio of the
fifth power of the distance? We have the exponent −6, or −5,
in place of the exponent −2, but it is always an exponent. |
This conception was not without grandeur; it was seductive,
and many among us have not finally renounced it; they know that
one will attain the ultimate elements of things only by patiently
disentangling the complicated skein that our senses give us; that
it is necessary to advance step by step, neglecting no intermediary;
that our fathers were wrong in wishing to skip stations;
but they believe that when one shall have arrived at these ultimate
elements, there again will be found the majestic simplicity
of celestial mechanics. |
I will explain myself; how did the ancients understand law?
It was for them an internal harmony, static, so to say, and immutable;
or else it was like a model that nature tried to imitate.
For us a law is something quite different; it is a constant relation
between the phenomenon of to-day and that of to-morrow;
in a word, it is a differential equation. |
Behold the ideal form of physical law; well, it is Newton's law
which first clothed it forth. If then one has acclimated this form
in physics, it is precisely by copying as far as possible this law of
Newton, that is by imitating celestial mechanics. This is, moreover,
the idea I have tried to bring out in Chapter VI. |
Well, in regard to the universe, the principle of the conservation
of energy is able to render us the same service. The universe
is also a machine, much more complicated than all those of
industry, of which almost all the parts are profoundly hidden
from us; but in observing the motion of those that we can see,
we are able, by the aid of this principle, to draw conclusions
which remain true whatever may be the details of the invisible
mechanism which animates them. |
The application of these five or six general principles to the
different physical phenomena is sufficient for our learning of
them all that we could reasonably hope to know of them. The
most remarkable example of this new mathematical physics is,
beyond question, Maxwell's electromagnetic theory of light. |
We know nothing as to what the ether is, how its molecules are
disposed, whether they attract or repel each other; but we know
that this medium transmits at the same time the optical perturbations
and the electrical perturbations; we know that this transmission
must take place in conformity with the general principles
of mechanics, and that suffices us for the establishment of
the equations of the electromagnetic field. |
These principles are results of experiments boldly generalized;
but they seem to derive from their very generality a high degree
of certainty. In fact, the more general they are, the more frequent
are the opportunities to check them, and the verifications
multiplying, taking the most varied, the most unexpected forms,
end by no longer leaving place for doubt. |
When I speak thus, you no doubt think of radium, that grand
revolutionist of the present time, and in fact I shall come back
to it presently; but there is something else. It is not alone the
conservation of energy which is in question; all the other principles
are equally in danger, as we shall see in passing them successively
in review. |
We have striven to reconcile this apparent contradiction. If
the world tends toward uniformity, this is not because its ultimate
parts, at first unlike, tend to become less and less different;
it is because, shifting at random, they end by blending. For an
eye which should distinguish all the elements, the variety would
remain always as great; each grain of this dust preserves its
originality and does not model itself on its neighbors; but as the
blend becomes more and more intimate, our gross senses perceive
only the uniformity. This is why, for example, temperatures
tend to a level, without the possibility of going backwards. |
A drop of wine falls into a glass of water; whatever may be
the law of the internal motion of the liquid, we shall soon see it
colored of a uniform rosy tint, and however much from this
moment one may shake it afterwards, the wine and the water
do not seem capable of again separating. Here we have the
type of the irreversible physical phenomenon: to hide a grain of
barley in a heap of wheat, this is easy; afterwards to find it
again and get it out, this is practically impossible. All this
Maxwell and Boltzmann have explained; but the one who has
seen it most clearly, in a book too little read because it is a little
difficult to read, is Gibbs, in his `Elementary Principles of Statistical
Mechanics.' |
I well know what will be said: It is not its absolute velocity
that is measured, it is its velocity in relation to the ether. How
unsatisfactory that is! Is it not evident that from the principle
so understood we could no longer infer anything? It could no
longer tell us anything just because it would no longer fear any
contradiction. If we succeed in measuring anything, we shall
always be free to say that this is not the absolute velocity, and if
it is not the velocity in relation to the ether, it might always be
the velocity in relation to some new unknown fluid with which
we might fill space. |
Indeed, experiment has taken upon itself to ruin this interpretation
of the principle of relativity; all attempts to measure the
velocity of the earth in relation to the ether have led to negative
results. This time experimental physics has been more
faithful to the principle than mathematical physics; the theorists,
to put in accord their other general views, would not have spared
it; but experiment has been stubborn in confirming it. The
means have been varied; finally Michelson pushed precision to
its last limits; nothing came of it. It is precisely to explain
this obstinacy that the mathematicians are forced to-day to employ
all their ingenuity. |
The analysis of the facts permits us to be still more precise.
Imagine, for example, a Hertzian oscillator, like those used in
wireless telegraphy; it sends out energy in every direction; but
we can provide it with a parabolic mirror, as Hertz did with his
smallest oscillators, so as to send all the energy produced in a
single direction. What happens then according to the theory?
The apparatus recoils, as if it were a cannon and the projected
energy a ball; and that is contrary to the principle of Newton,
since our projectile here has no mass, it is not matter, it is energy.
The case is still the same, moreover, with a beacon light provided
with a reflector, since light is nothing but a perturbation of the
electromagnetic field. This beacon light should recoil as if the
light it sends out were a projectile. What is the force that
should produce this recoil? It is what is called the Maxwell-Bartholi
pressure. It is very minute, and it has been difficult
to put it in evidence even with the most sensitive radiometers;
but it suffices that it exists. |
If all the energy issuing from our oscillator falls on a receiver,
this will act as if it had received a mechanical shock, which will
represent in a sense the compensation of the oscillator's recoil;
the reaction will be equal to the action, but it will not be simultaneous;
the receiver will move on, but not at the moment when
the oscillator recoils. If the energy propagates itself indefinitely
without encountering a receiver, the compensation will never
occur. |
And then the suppositions that it would be necessary to make
on the movements of the ether are not very satisfactory. If the
electric charges double, it would be natural to imagine that the
velocities of the diverse atoms of ether double also; but, for the
compensation, it would be necessary that the mean velocity of
the ether quadruple. |
The calculations of Abraham and the experiments of Kaufmann
have then shown that the mechanical mass, properly so
called, is null, and that the mass of the electrons, or, at least, of
the negative electrons, is of exclusively electrodynamic origin.
This is what forces us to change the definition of mass; we can
not any longer distinguish mechanical mass and electrodynamic
mass, since then the first would vanish; there is no mass other
than electrodynamic inertia. But in this case the mass can no
longer be constant; it augments with the velocity, and it even
depends on the direction, and a body animated by a notable
velocity will not oppose the same inertia to the forces which tend
to deflect it from its route, as to those which tend to accelerate
or to retard its progress. |
There is still a resource; the ultimate elements of bodies are
electrons, some charged negatively, the others charged positively.
The negative electrons have no mass, this is understood; but the
positive electrons, from the little we know of them, seem much
greater. Perhaps they have, besides their electrodynamic mass,
a true mechanical mass. The real mass of a body would, then,
be the sum of the mechanical masses of its positive electrons, the
negative electrons not counting; mass so defined might still be
constant. |
Need I point out that the fall of Lavoisier's principle involves
that of Newton's? This latter signifies that the center of gravity
of an isolated system moves in a straight line; but if there is no
longer a constant mass, there is no longer a center of gravity,
we no longer know even what this is. This is why I said above
that the experiments on the cathode rays appeared to justify
the doubts of Lorentz concerning Newton's principle. |
No more for an observer, carried along himself in a translation
he does not suspect, could any apparent velocity surpass
that of light; and this would be then a contradiction, if we did
not recall that this observer would not use the same clocks as a
fixed observer, but, indeed, clocks marking 'local time.' |
Here we are then facing a question I content myself with stating.
If there is no longer any mass, what becomes of Newton's
law? Mass has two aspects: it is at the same time a coefficient of
inertia and an attracting mass entering as factor into Newtonian
attraction. If the coefficient of inertia is not constant, can the
attracting mass be? That is the question. |
The explanations proposed were numerous; but in such case
we can not say, the more the better. In so far as no one of them
has prevailed over the others, we can not be sure there is a good
one among them. Since some time, however, one of these explanations
seems to be getting the upper hand and we may reasonably
hope that we hold the key to the mystery. |
Sir W. Ramsay has striven to show that radium is in process
of transformation, that it contains a store of energy enormous
but not inexhaustible. The transformation of radium then
would produce a million times more heat than all known transformations;
radium would wear itself out in 1,250 years; this is
quite short, and you see that we are at least certain to have this
point settled some hundreds of years from now. While waiting,
our doubts remain. |
In presence of this general collapse of the principles, what attitude
will mathematical physics take? And first, before too
much excitement, it is proper to ask if all that is really true.
All these derogations to the principles are encountered only
among infinitesimals; the microscope is necessary to see the
Brownian movement; electrons are very light; radium is very
rare, and one never has more than some milligrams of it at a
time. And, then, it may be asked whether, besides the infinitesimal
seen, there was not another infinitesimal unseen counterpoise
to the first. |
So there is an interlocutory question, and, as it seems, only
experiment can solve it. We shall, therefore, only have to hand
over the matter to the experimenters, and, while waiting for them
to finally decide the debate, not to preoccupy ourselves with these
disquieting problems, and to tranquilly continue our work as if
the principles were still uncontested. Certes, we have much to
do without leaving the domain where they may be applied in all
security; we have enough to employ our activity during this
period of doubts. |
It is a question before all of endeavoring to obtain a more
satisfactory theory of the electrodynamics of bodies in motion.
It is there especially, as I have sufficiently shown above, that
difficulties accumulate. It is useless to heap up hypotheses,
we can not satisfy all the principles at once; so far, one has
succeeded in safeguarding some only on condition of sacrificing
the others; but all hope of obtaining better results is not yet
lost. Let us take, then, the theory of Lorentz, turn it in all
senses, modify it little by little, and perhaps everything will
arrange itself. |
Thus in place of supposing that bodies in motion undergo a
contraction in the sense of the motion, and that this contraction
is the same whatever be the nature of these bodies and the forces
to which they are otherwise subjected, could we not make a more
simple and natural hypothesis? We might imagine, for example,
that it is the ether which is modified when it is in relative motion
in reference to the material medium which penetrates it, that,
when it is thus modified, it no longer transmits perturbations
with the same velocity in every direction. It might transmit
more rapidly those which are propagated parallel to the motion
of the medium, whether in the same sense or in the opposite sense,
and less rapidly those which are propagated perpendicularly.
The wave surfaces would no longer be spheres, but ellipsoids,
and we could dispense with that extraordinary contraction of all
bodies. |
At least this is true in first approximation, but the case would
be no longer the same if we could appreciate the thousandths of
a second. Then it would be seen that the amplitude of the oscillation
depends not alone on the variation of the motion, a variation
which is well known, since it is the motion of our globe on
its elliptic orbit, but on the mean value of this motion, so that
the constant of aberration would not be quite the same for all the
stars, and the differences would tell us the absolute motion of the
earth in space. |
This, then, would be, under another form, the ruin of the principle
of relativity. We are far, it is true, from appreciating the
thousandth of a second, but, after all, say some, the earth's total
absolute velocity is perhaps much greater than its relative velocity
with respect to the sun. If, for example, it were 300 kilometers
per second in place of 30, this would suffice to make the
phenomenon observable. |
I believe that in reasoning thus one admits a too simple theory
of aberration. Michelson has shown us, I have told you, that the
physical procedures are powerless to put in evidence absolute
motion; I am persuaded that the same will be true of the astronomic
procedures, however far precision be carried. |
However that may be, the data astronomy will furnish us in
this regard will some day be precious to the physicist. Meanwhile,
I believe that the theorists, recalling the experience of
Michelson, may anticipate a negative result, and that they would
accomplish a useful work in constructing a theory of aberration
which would explain this in advance. |
That has not yet been accounted for, and I believe that there
we have one of the most important secrets of nature. A Japanese
physicist, M. Nagaoka, has recently proposed an explanation;
according to him, atoms are composed of a large positive
electron surrounded by a ring formed of a great number of very
small negative electrons. Such is the planet Saturn with its
rings. This is a very interesting attempt, but not yet wholly
satisfactory; this attempt should be renewed. We will penetrate,
so to speak, into the inmost recess of matter. And from
the particular point of view which we to-day occupy, when we
know why the vibrations of incandescent bodies differ thus from
ordinary elastic vibrations, why the electrons do not behave like
the matter which is familiar to us, we shall better comprehend the
dynamics of electrons and it will be perhaps more easy for us
to reconcile it with the principles. |
Have you not written, you might say if you wished to seek a
quarrel with me—have you not written that the principles,
though of experimental origin, are now unassailable by experiment
because they have become conventions? And now you
have just told us that the most recent conquests of experiment
put these principles in danger. |
Well, formerly I was right and to-day I am not wrong. Formerly
I was right, and what is now happening is a new proof of
it. Take, for example, the calorimetric experiment of Curie on
radium. Is it possible to reconcile it with the principle of the
conservation of energy? This has been attempted in many ways.
But there is among them one I should like you to notice; this is
not the explanation which tends to-day to prevail, but it is one
of those which have been proposed. It has been conjectured
that radium was only an intermediary, that it only stored radiations
of unknown nature which flashed through space in every
direction, traversing all bodies, save radium, without being altered
by this passage and without exercising any action upon
them. Radium alone took from them a little of their energy and
afterward gave it out to us in various forms. |
What an advantageous explanation, and how convenient!
First, it is unverifiable and thus irrefutable. Then again it will
serve to account for any derogation whatever to Mayer's principle;
it answers in advance not only the objection of Curie, but
all the objections that future experimenters might accumulate.
This new and unknown energy would serve for everything. |
As I have said, we have already passed through a like crisis.
I have shown you that in the second mathematical physics, that
of the principles, we find traces of the first, that of central
forces; it will be just the same if we must know a third. Just so
with the animal that exuviates, that breaks its too narrow carapace
and makes itself a fresh one; under the new envelope one
will recognize the essential traits of the organism which have
persisted. |
We can not foresee in what way we are about to expand; perhaps
it is the kinetic theory of gases which is about to undergo
development and serve as model to the others. Then the facts
which first appeared to us as simple thereafter would be merely
resultants of a very great number of elementary facts which only
the laws of chance would make cooperate for a common end.
Physical law would then assume an entirely new aspect; it would
no longer be solely a differential equation, it would take the character
of a statistical law. |
Among the writings inspired by this tendency it is proper to
place in the first rank those of M. LeRoy. This thinker is not
only a philosopher and a writer of the greatest merit, but he has
acquired a deep knowledge of the exact and physical sciences,
and even has shown rare powers of mathematical invention. Let
us recapitulate in a few words his doctrine, which has given rise
to numerous discussions. |
However great my esteem for M. LeRoy's talent, whatever the
ingenuity of this thesis, I can not wholly accept it. Certes, I
am in accord on many points with M. LeRoy, and he has even
cited, in support of his view, various passages of my writings
which I am by no means disposed to reject. I think myself only
the more bound to explain why I can not go with him all the way. |
The fact is that anti-intellectualistic philosophy in rejecting
analysis and 'discourse,' just by that condemns itself to being
intransmissible; it is a philosophy essentially internal, or, at the
very least, only its negations can be transmitted; what wonder
then that for an external observer it takes the shape of scepticism? |
And, yet, would it not be more logical in remaining silent?
See, you have written long articles; for that, it was necessary
to use words. And therein have you not been much more 'discursive'
and consequently much farther from life and truth than
the animal who simply lives without philosophizing? Would
not this animal be the true philosopher? |
Pardon these brief reflections and pardon also their brevity,
scarcely skimming the question. The process of intellectualism
is not the subject I wish to treat: I wish to speak of science, and
about it there is no doubt; by definition, so to speak, it will be
intellectualistic or it will not be at all. Precisely the question is,
whether it will be. |
It is thus that men, desirous of diversion, have instituted rules
of play, like those of tric-trac for instance, which, better than
science itself, could rely upon the proof by universal consent.
It is thus likewise that, unable to choose, but forced to choose, we
toss up a coin, head or tail to win. |
If I say, to make hydrogen cause an acid to act on zinc, I formulate
a rule which succeeds; I could have said, make distilled
water act on gold; that also would have been a rule, only it would
not have succeeded. If, therefore, scientific 'recipes' have a
value, as rule of action, it is because we know they succeed, generally
at least. But to know this is to know something and then
why tell us we can know nothing? |
Science foresees, and it is because it foresees that it can be
useful and serve as rule of action. I well know that its previsions
are often contradicted by the event; that shows that
science is imperfect, and if I add that it will always remain so,
I am certain that this is a prevision which, at least, will never
be contradicted. Always the scientist is less often mistaken
than a prophet who should predict at random. Besides the
progress though slow is continuous, so that scientists, though
more and more bold, are less and less misled. This is little, but
it is enough. |
I well know that M. LeRoy has somewhere said that science
was mistaken oftener than one thought, that comets sometimes
played tricks on astronomers, that scientists, who apparently are
men, did not willingly speak of their failures, and that, if they
should speak of them, they would have to count more defeats
than victories. |
That day, M. LeRoy evidently overreached himself. If science
did not succeed, it could not serve as rule of action; whence
would it get its value? Because it is 'lived,' that is, because we
love it and believe in it? The alchemists had recipes for making
gold, they loved them and had faith in them, and yet our recipes
are the good ones, although our faith be less lively, because they
succeed. |
It should not even be said that action is the goal of science;
should we condemn studies of the star Sirius, under pretext that
we shall probably never exercise any influence on that star? To
my eyes, on the contrary, it is the knowledge which is the end,
and the action which is the means. If I felicitate myself on the
industrial development, it is not alone because it furnishes a
facile argument to the advocates of science; it is above all because
it gives to the scientist faith in himself and also because it offers
him an immense field of experience where he clashes against
forces too colossal to be tampered with. Without this ballast,
who knows whether he would not quit solid ground, seduced by
the mirage of some scholastic novelty, or whether he would not
despair, believing he had fashioned only a dream? |
This distinction between the fact in the rough and the scientific
fact does not by itself appear to me illegitimate. But I
complain first that the boundary has not been traced either
exactly or precisely; and then that the author has seemed to suppose
that the crude fact, not being scientific, is outside of science. |
The examples given by M. LeRoy have greatly astonished me.
The first is taken from the notion of atom. The atom chosen as
example of fact! I avow that this choice has so disconcerted
me that I prefer to say nothing about it. I have evidently misunderstood
the author's thought and I could not fruitfully discuss
it. |
Finally, M. LeRoy cites the rotation of the earth; it has been
answered: but this is not a fact, and he has replied: it was one
for Galileo, who affirmed it, as for the inquisitor, who denied it.
It always remains that this is not a fact in the same sense as
those just spoken of and that to give them the same name is to
expose one's self to many confusions. |
Or again: when I make an experiment I should subject the
result to certain corrections, because I know I must have made
errors. These errors are of two kinds, some are accidental and
these I shall correct by taking the mean; the others are systematic
and I shall be able to correct those only by a thorough study of
their causes. The first result obtained is then the fact in the
rough, while the scientific fact is the final result after the
finished corrections. |
And this is not all: the first stage also should be subdivided,
and not between these two subdivisions will be the least distance;
it is necessary to distinguish between the impression of obscurity
felt by one witnessing an eclipse, and the affirmation: It grows
dark, which this impression extorts from him. In a sense it is
the first which is the only true fact in the rough, and the second
is already a sort of scientific fact. |
Is there something to change in all that when we pass to the
following stages? When I observe a galvanometer, as I have
just said, if I ask an ignorant visitor: Is the current passing?
he looks at the wire to try to see something pass; but if I put the
same question to my assistant who understands my language, he
will know I mean: Does the spot move? and he will look at the
scale. |
Here then is one same statement which suits a very great number
of facts absolutely different. Why? It is because I assume
a law according to which, whenever such a mechanical effect shall
happen, such a chemical effect will happen also. Previous experiments,
very numerous, have never shown this law to fail, and
then I have understood that I could express by the same statement
two facts so invariably bound one to the other. |
When I am asked: Is the current passing? I can understand
that that means: Will such a mechanical effect happen? But I
can understand also: Will such a chemical effect happen? I
shall then verify either the existence of the mechanical effect, or
that of the chemical effect; that will be indifferent, since in both
cases the answer must be the same. |
You ask me: Is there a current? I try whether the mechanical
effect exists, I ascertain it and I answer: Yes, there is a current.
You understand at once that that means that the mechanical
effect exists, and that the chemical effect, that I have not investigated,
exists likewise. Imagine now, supposing an impossibility,
the law we believe true, not to be, and the chemical effect not to
exist. Under this hypothesis there will be two distinct facts, the
one directly observed and which is true, the other inferred and
which is false. It may strictly be said that we have created the
second. So that error is the part of man's personal collaboration
in the creation of the scientific fact. |
But if we can say that the fact in question is false, is this not
just because it is not a free and arbitrary creation of our mind, a
disguised convention, in which case it would be neither true nor
false. And in fact it was verifiable; I had not made the verification,
but I could have made it. If I answered amiss, it was because
I chose to reply too quickly, without having asked nature,
who alone knew the secret. |
When, after an experiment, I correct the accidental and systematic
errors to bring out the scientific fact, the case is the same;
the scientific fact will never be anything but the crude fact translated
into another language. When I shall say: It is such an
hour, that will be a short way of saying: There is such a relation
between the hour indicated by my clock, and the hour it marked
at the moment of the passing of such a star and such another
star across the meridian. And this convention of language once
adopted, when I shall be asked: Is it such an hour? it will not
depend upon me to answer yes or no. |
It is true that at the last stage things change. Does the
earth rotate? Is this a verifiable fact? Could Galileo and the
Grand Inquisitor, to settle the matter, appeal to the witness of
their senses? On the contrary, they were in accord about the
appearances, and whatever had been the accumulated experiences,
they would have remained in accord with regard to the
appearances without ever agreeing on their interpretation. It
is just on that account that they were obliged to have recourse
to procedures of discussion so unscientific. |
After all, what do you mean when you speak of this free
creation of the scientific fact and when you take as example the
astronomer who intervenes actively in the phenomenon of the
eclipse by bringing his clock? Do you mean: The eclipse happened
at nine o'clock; but if the astronomer had wished it to
happen at ten, that depended only on him, he had only to
advance his clock an hour? |
What then remains of M. LeRoy's thesis? This remains: the
scientist intervenes actively in choosing the facts worth observing.
An isolated fact has by itself no interest; it becomes interesting
if one has reason to think that it may aid in the prediction
of other facts; or better, if, having been predicted, its verification
is the confirmation of a law. Who shall choose the facts
which, corresponding to these conditions, are worthy the freedom
of the city in science? This is the free activity of the scientist. |
And that is not all. I have said that the scientific fact is the
translation of a crude fact into a certain language; I should add
that every scientific fact is formed of many crude facts. This is
sufficiently shown by the examples cited above. For instance,
for the hour of the eclipse my clock marked the hour α at the
instant of the eclipse; it marked the hour β at the moment of the
last transit of the meridian of a certain star that we take as
origin of right ascensions; it marked the hour γ at the moment
of the preceding transit of this same star. There are three distinct
facts (still it will be noticed that each of them results itself
from two simultaneous facts in the rough; but let us pass this
over). In place of that I say: The eclipse happened at the hour
24 (α−β) / (β−γ), and the three facts are combined in a single
scientific fact. I have concluded that the three readings, α, β, γ
made on my clock at three different moments lacked interest and
that the only thing interesting was the combination (α−β) / (β−γ)
of the three. In this conclusion is found the free activity of my
mind. |
Recall first the examples he has given. When I say: Phosphorus
melts at 44°, I think I am enunciating a law; in reality
it is just the definition of phosphorus; if one should discover a
body which, possessing otherwise all the properties of phosphorus,
did not melt at 44°, we should give it another name, that is all,
and the law would remain true. |
Just so when I say: Heavy bodies falling freely pass over
spaces proportional to the squares of the times, I only give the
definition of free fall. Whenever the condition shall not be
fulfilled, I shall say that the fall is not free, so that the law
will never be wrong. It is clear that if laws were reduced to that,
they could not serve in prediction; then they would be good for
nothing, either as means of knowledge or as principle of action. |
When I say: Phosphorus melts at 44°, I mean by that: All
bodies possessing such or such a property (to wit, all the properties
of phosphorus, save fusing-point) fuse at 44°. So understood,
my proposition is indeed a law, and this law may be useful
to me, because if I meet a body possessing these properties
I shall be able to predict that it will fuse at 44°. |